The role of homo oeconomicus in the political economy of James Buchanan

Constitutional Political Economy - Tập 25 - Trang 2-17 - 2014
Gebhard Kirchgässner1
1SIAW-HSG, University of St. Gallen, St. Gallen, Switzerland

Tóm tắt

Whenever the economic model of behavior is to be applied, the utility function has—at least somewhat—to be specified. Buchanan generally prefers to apply a rather narrow version. However, he acknowledges that it is hardly possible to explain actual behavior of individuals with such a version, so in performing empirical economic research he accepts that we have to use a more open one. He also acknowledges that people might behave differently in markets than they do in politics; other-regarding behavior might be more pronounced in politics as compared to markets. Which version should be applied in constitutional economics, however, is a different question. Following a long ongoing tradition in political philosophy, he insists that—for methodological reasons—the narrow version is the correct one to be applied; this is the way to compare different sets of rules when analyzing the possible abuse of power by rulers in order to prevent it as far as possible. The same should also be taken into account when analyzing the process of policy advice. The narrow homo oeconomicus model should, however, not be misunderstood as a normative prescription.

Tài liệu tham khảo

Alchian, A. A., & Allen, W. R. (1968). University economics (2nd ed.). Belmont (CA): Wadsworth Press.

Andreoni, J. (1988). Privately produced public goods in a large economy. Journal of Public Economics, 35, 57–73.

Apel, K.-O., & Kettner, M. (Eds.). (1992). Zur Anwendung der Diskursethik in Politik, Recht und Wissenschaft. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

Buchanan, J. M. (1969b). Is Economics the Science of Choice? In E. Streisler (Ed.). Roads to freedom: Essays in honour of Friedrich A. von Hayek (pp. 47–64). London: Routledge and Keegan Paul; reprinted in J. M. Buchanan (1987c), pp. 35–50.

Buchanan, J. M. (1979a). Politics without romance: A sketch of positive public choice theory and its normative implications. IHS Journal, 3, B1–B11; reprinted in The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 1: The logical foundations of constitutional liberty (pp. 45–59). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1999.

Buchanan, J. M. (1979b). Professor Alchian on economic method. In J. M. Buchanan, What Should Economists Do? (pp. 65–79). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund; reprinted in The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 12: Economic inquiry and its logic (pp. 128–138). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2000.

Buchanan, J. M. (1982b). The domain of subjective economics: Between predictive science and moral philosophy. In I. M. Kirzner (Ed.). Method, process, and austrian economics: Essays in honor of Ludwig von Mises (pp. 7–20). Lexington (Mass.): D. C. Heath; reprinted in The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 17: Moral science and moral order (pp. 24–39). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2001.

Buchanan, J. M. (1987b). Constitutional economics. In The new palgrave, a dictionary of economics (Vol. 1, pp. 585–588). London: Macmillan.

Buchanan, J. M. (1989). Rational choice models in the social sciences. In R. D. Tollison & V. J. Vanberg (Eds.). Explorations into constitutional economics (pp. 37–50). College Station: Texas A&M University Press; reprinted in The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 17: Moral science and moral order (pp. 55–70). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2001.

Buchanan, J. M. (1992). Virginia political economy: Some personal reflections. In J. M. Buchanan, Better than playing: And other personal essays (pp. 93–107). Chicago: University of Chicago Press; reprinted in The collected works of James M. Buchanan, Volume 19: Ideas, persons, events (pp. 50–63). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2001.

Carnap, R. (1932). Die physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenschaft. Erkenntnis, 2, 432–465.

Habermas, J. (1971). Vorbereitende Bemerkungen zu einer Theorie der kommunikativen Kompetenz. In J. Habermas & N. Luhmann (Eds.), Theorie der Gesellschaft oder Sozialtechnologie (pp. 101–141). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

Kelman, S. (1987). ‘Public choice’ and public spirit. Public Interest, 87, 80–94.

Kirchgässner, G. (1997). Auf der Suche nach dem Gespenst des Ökonomismus: Einige Bemerkungen über Tausch, Märkte, und die Ökonomisierung der Lebensverhältnisse. Analyse und Kritik, 19, 127–152.

Kirchgässner, G. (2010). On minimal morals. European Journal of Political Economy, 26, 330–339.

Maital, S. (1986). Prometheus rebound: On welfare-improving constraints. Eastern Economic Journal, 12, 237–244.

Mill, J. S. (1861). Considerations on representative government. Reprint: London: Parker, Son, and Bourn, 1890.

Popper, K. R. (1935). Logik der Forschung. Vienna: Julius Springer; English translation: Logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson (1959).

Popper, K. R. (1945). The open society and its enemies, vol. I, The spell of Plato. London: Routledge and Sons.

Simon, H. A. (1978). Rationality as process and as product of thought. American Economic Review, Papers and Proceedings, 68(2), 1–16.

Smith, A. (1759). Theory of moral sentiments. London: Millar.

Wicksteed, P. H. (1910). The common sense of political economy (Vol. I). London: Macmillan (London: Routledge and Sons, 1933).