Thinking things and feeling things: on an alleged discontinuity in folk metaphysics of mind

Springer Science and Business Media LLC - Tập 12 - Trang 703-725 - 2012
Mark Phelan1, Adam Arico2, Shaun Nichols2
1Lawrence University, Appleton, USA
2Department of Philosophy, University of Arizona, Tucson, USA

Tóm tắt

According to the discontinuity view, people recognize a deep discontinuity between phenomenal and intentional states, such that they refrain from attributing feelings and experiences to entities that do not have the right kind of body, though they may attribute thoughts to entities that lack a biological body, like corporations, robots, and disembodied souls. We examine some of the research that has been used to motivate the discontinuity view. Specifically, we focus on experiments that examine people's aptness judgments for various mental state ascriptions to groups. These studies seem to reveal that people are more inclined to think of groups as having intentionality than as having phenomenology. Combined with the fact that groups obviously lack a single biological body, this has been taken as evidence that people operate according to the relevant discontinuity. However, these studies support discontinuity only on the assumption that the experimental participants are interpreting the relevant group mental state ascriptions in a specific way. We present evidence that people are not interpreting these ascriptions in a way that supports discontinuity. Instead, we argue that people generally interpret group mental state ascriptions distributively, as attributions of mental states to various group members.

Tài liệu tham khảo

Arico, A. (2010). Folk psychology, consciousness, and context effects. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(3), 371–393. Arico, A. (2012). Breaking out of moral typecasting. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, in press Arico, A., Fiala, B., Goldberg, R., & Nichols, S. (2011). Folk psychology of consciousness. Mind and Language, 26(3), 327–352. Bach, K. (2001). You don't say? Synthese, 128, 15–44. Block, N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18(2), 227–287. Bloom, P., & Veres, C. (1999). The perceived intentionality of groups. Cognition, 71, B1–B9. Bratman, M. (1993). Shared intention. Ethics, 104, 97–113. Bratman, M. (1999). Faces of intention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cullen, S. (2009). Survey-driven romanticism. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 275–296. Fiala, B., Arico, A., & Nichols, S. (2011). On the Psychological origins of dualism: Dual-process cognition and the explanatory gap. In E. Slingerland, & M. Collard (Eds.), Creating consilience: issues and case studies in the integration of the sciences and humanities (pp. 88–109). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gilbert, M. (1996). On social facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral typecasting: divergent perceptions of moral agents and moral patients. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96, 505–520. Gray, H., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2007). Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 315, 619. Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Report the Google finding in “Mind perception is the essence of morality”. Psychological Inquiry, 23(2), 101–124. Heider, F., & Simmel, M. (1944). An experimental study of apparent behavior. American Journal of Psychology, 57, 243–259. Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: classical and contemporary readings (pp. 520–533). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Huebner, B. (2008). Distributing cognition: A defense of collective mentality. Ph.D. dissertation. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina. Huebner, B., Bruno, M., & Sarkissian, H. (2010). What does the nation of China think about phenomenal states? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 225–243. Knobe, J., & Prinz, J. (2008). Intuitions about consciousness: experimental studies. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, 7, 67–83. Kriegel, U. (2003). Is intentionality dependent upon consciousness? Philosophical Studies, 116(3), 271–307. Landman, F. (1989a). Groups, I. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(5), 559–605. Landman, F. (1989b). Groups, II. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(6), 723–744. Link, G. (1984). Hydras. On the logic of relative clause constructions with multiple heads. In F. Landman & F. Veltmann (Eds.), Varieties of formal semantics. Dordrecht: Foris. Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review, 4, 435–450. Pettit, P. (2003). “Groups with minds of their own.” In F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics (pp. 167–193). New York: Rowan and Littlefield. Phelan, M. (2010). The inadequacy of paraphrase is the dogma of metaphor. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91, 481–506. Robbins, P., & Jack, A. (2006). The phenomenal stance. Philosophical Studies, 127(1), 59–85. Rosenthal, D. (1997). A theory of consciousness. In F. Block & Güzeldere (Eds.), The nature of consciousness (pp. 729–753). Cambridge: MIT Press. Schwarz, N. (1996). Cognition and communication: judgmental biases, research methods, and the logic of conversation. Mahwah: Erlbaum. Searle, J. (1990). Collective intentions and actions. In P. Cohen, J. Morgan, & M. E. Pollack (Eds.), Intentions in communication. Cambridge: Bradford Books, MIT press. Searle, J. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: Free Press. Strawson, G. (2005). Real intentionality v. 2: why intentionality entails consciousness. Synthesis Philosophica, 2(40), 279–297. Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2009). How to study folk intuitions about consciousness. Philosophical Psychology, 22(1), 21–35. Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2010). Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies, 151(2), 299–327. Tollefsen, D. (2002). Organizations as true believers. Journal of Social Philosophy, 33, 395–410. Velleman, D. (1997). “How to Share an Intention”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57, 29–50.