The limits of Humeanism

European Journal for Philosophy of Science - Tập 8 - Trang 671-687 - 2018
Jesse M. Mulder1
1Utrecht, The Netherlands

Tóm tắt

Humeans take reality to be devoid of ‘necessary connections’: things just happen. Laws of nature are to be understood in terms of what ‘just happens’, not vice versa. Here the Humean needs some conception of what it is that ‘just happens’ – a conception of the Humean mosaic. Lewis’s Humeanism incorporates such a conception in the form of a Lewis-style metaphysics of objects, properties, and modality. Newer versions of Humeanism about laws of nature, such as the Better Best Systems approach (BBS), typically reject such a Lewisian metaphysics, but it remains unclear what they can offer in its place. By exploring different candidate conceptions, this paper sheds light on the limits of Humeanism about laws of nature: not all conceptions of the Humean mosaic form a suitable basis for a Humean theory of laws. In fact, only a metaphysics roughly in line with Lewis’s will do. The paper ends with a tentative generalization of this result, thus pointing to the ‘limit’ of Humeanism in general: taking the Humean way of thinking to its limit results in a rejection of the whole idea of such a mosaic – and hence of Humean mosaic-based accounts of anything.

Tài liệu tham khảo

Albert, D. Z. (2001). Time and chance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Anscombe, G.E.M. (1971). Causality and determinism. In her Collected philosophical papers, vol. II: Metaphysics and the philosophy of mind (pp. 133–47). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 1981. Beebee, H. (2000). The non-governing conception of laws of nature. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61(3), 571–594. Braithwaite, R. B. (1927). “The idea of necessary connexion” (I). Mind, 36(144), 467–477. Braithwaite, R. B. (1928). “The idea of necessary connexion” (II). Mind, 37(145), 62–72. Callender, C., & Cohen, J. (2010). Special sciences, conspiracy and the better best system account of lawhood. Erkenntnis, 73(3), 427–447. Cartwright, N. (1984). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cohen, J., & Callender, C. (2009). A better best systems account of lawhood. Philosophical Studies, 145(1), 1–34. Dorr, C. (2005). What we disagree about when we disagree about ontology. In M. E. Kalderon (Ed.), Fictionalism in metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press Ch. 8. Dunn, J. (2011). Fried eggs, thermodynamics, and the special sciences. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(1), 71–98. Earman, J., & Roberts, J. T. (2005a). Contact with the nomic: a challenge for deniers of Humean Supervenience about laws of nature, part I: Humean Supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(1), 1–22. Earman, J., & Roberts, J. T. (2005b). Contact with the nomic: a challenge for deniers of Humean Supervenience about laws of nature, part II: the epistemological argument for Humean Supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 71(2), 253–286. Eklund, M. (2008). The picture of reality as an amorphous lump. In T. Sider, J. Hawthorne, & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell Ch 9.2. Frisch, M. (2011). From Arbuthnot to Boltzmann: the past hypothesis, the best system, and the special sciences. Philosophy of Science, 78(5), 1001–1011. Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, fiction and forecast. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Hume, D. 2007 (1748). In P. Millican (Ed.) An enquiry concerning human understanding. New York: Oxford University Press Hume, D. 2010 (1740). A treatise of human nature. New York: Oxford University Press Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Lewis, D. (1986a). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Lewis, D. (1986b). Philosophical papers: Volume II. New York: Oxford University Press. Lewis, D. (1991). Parts of classes. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Lewis, D. (1994). Humean Supervenience debugged. Mind, 103(412), 473–490. Loewer, B. (1996). Humean Supervenience and laws of nature. Philosophical Topics, 24, 101–127. Loewer, B. (2012). Two accounts of laws and time. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 115–137. Mill, J. S. (1865). An examination of sir William Hamilton’s philosophy. London: Longman. Millgram, E. (2009). Hard truths. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. Millgram, E. (2011). Lewis’s epicycles, possible worlds, and the mysteries of modality. http://www.elijahmillgram.net/publications/mrms.pdf. Mulder, J. M. (2013). The essentialist inference. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(4), 755–769. Mulder, J. M. (2016). A vital challenge to materialism. Philosophy, 91(2), 153–182. Roberts, J. T. (2008). The law-governed universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schrenk, M. (2006). A theory for special science laws. In H. Bohse and S. Walter (Eds.) Selected papers contributed to the sections of GAP.6. Paderborn: Mentis Verlag. Sidelle, A. (1998). A sweater unraveled: following one thread of thought for avoiding coincident entities. Noûs, 32(4), 423–448. Sidelle, A. (2010). Modality and objects. The Philosophical Quarterly, 60(238), 109–125. Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism. An ontology of persistence and time. New York: Oxford University Press. Sosa, E. (1993). Putnam’s pragmatic realism. The Journal of Philosophy, 90(12), 605–626. Sosa, E. (1999). Existential relativity. Midwest studies in philosophy, 23(1), 132–143. Stroud, B. (2011). Engagement and metaphysical dissatisfaction: Modality and value. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Swartz, N. (1985). The concept of physical law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, B. (1993). On natural properties in metaphysics. Mind, 102(405), 81–100. Ward, B. (2002). Humeanism without Humean Supervenience: a projectivist account of laws and possibilities. Philosophical Studies, 107(3), 191–208.