Testing lexicographic semiorders as models of decision making: Priority dominance, integration, interaction, and transitivity
Tài liệu tham khảo
Bernoulli, 1738, Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis, Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropoliannae, 5, 175
Birnbaum, 1973, The Devil rides again: correlation as an index of fit, Psychological Bulletin, 79, 239, 10.1037/h0033853
Birnbaum, 1974, The nonadditivity of personality impressions, Journal of Experimental Psychology, 102, 543, 10.1037/h0036014
Birnbaum, 1974, Reply to the Devil’s advocates: don’t confound model testing and measurement, Psychological Bulletin, 81, 854, 10.1037/h0037132
Birnbaum, 1997, Violations of monotonicity in judgment and decision making, 73
Birnbaum, 1999, Testing critical properties of decision making on the Internet, Psychological Science, 10, 399, 10.1111/1467-9280.00176
Birnbaum, 2004, Causes of Allais common consequence paradoxes: an experimental dissection, Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 48, 87, 10.1016/j.jmp.2004.01.001
Birnbaum, 2004, Tests of rank-dependent utility and cumulative prospect theory in gambles represented by natural frequencies: effects of format, event framing, and branch splitting, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 95, 40, 10.1016/j.obhdp.2004.05.004
Birnbaum, 2005, A comparison of five models that predict violations of first-order stochastic dominance in risky decision making, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 31, 263, 10.1007/s11166-005-5103-9
Birnbaum, 2005, Three new tests of independence that differentiate models of risky decision making, Management Science, 51, 1346, 10.1287/mnsc.1050.0404
Birnbaum, 2008, Evaluation of the priority heuristic as a descriptive model of risky decision making: comment on Brandstatter et al (2006), Psychological Review, 115, 253, 10.1037/0033-295X.115.1.253
Birnbaum, 2008, New paradoxes of risky decision making, Psychological Review, 115, 463, 10.1037/0033-295X.115.2.463
Birnbaum, 2008, New tests of cumulative prospect theory and the priority heuristic: probability-outcome tradeoff with branch splitting, Judgment and Decision Making, 3, 304, 10.1017/S1930297500000875
Birnbaum, 2007, Gain-loss separability and coalescing in risky decision making, Management Science, 53, 1016, 10.1287/mnsc.1060.0592
Birnbaum, 1997, Tests of theories of decision making: violations of branch independence and distribution independence, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 71, 161, 10.1006/obhd.1997.2721
Birnbaum, 2007, Testing for intransitivity of preferences predicted by a lexicographic semiorder, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 104, 97, 10.1016/j.obhdp.2007.02.001
Birnbaum, 1990, A theory of comparative response times and “difference” judgments, Cognitive Psychology, 22, 184, 10.1016/0010-0285(90)90015-V
Birnbaum, 2008, Dimension integration: testing models without trade-offs, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 105, 122, 10.1016/j.obhdp.2007.07.002
Birnbaum, 1996, Violations of branch independence in choices between gambles, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 67, 91, 10.1006/obhd.1996.0067
Birnbaum, 1998, Testing descriptive utility theories: violations of stochastic dominance and cumulative independence, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 17, 49, 10.1023/A:1007739200913
Birnbaum, 2008, An experimental investigation of violations of transitivity in choice under uncertainty, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 37, 77, 10.1007/s11166-008-9043-z
Blavatskyy, 2006, Axiomatization of a preference for most probable winner, Theory and Decision, 60, 17, 10.1007/s11238-005-4753-z
Brandstätter, 2006, The priority heuristic: choices without tradeoffs, Psychological Review, 113, 409, 10.1037/0033-295X.113.2.409
Brandstätter, 2008, Risky Choice with Heuristics: reply to Birnbaum (2008), Johnson, Schulte-Mecklenbeck, & Willemsen (2008) and Rieger & Wang (2008), Psychological Review, 115, 281, 10.1037/0033-295X.115.1.281
Busemeyer, 1993, Decision Field Theory: a dynamic cognition approach to decision making, Psychological Review, 100, 432, 10.1037/0033-295X.100.3.432
Edwards, 1954, The theory of decision making, Psychological Bulletin, 51, 380, 10.1037/h0053870
Glöckner, 2008, Do people make decisions under risk based on ignorance? An empirical test of the priority heuristic against cumulative prospect theory, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 107, 75, 10.1016/j.obhdp.2008.02.003
González-Vallejo, 2002, Making trade-offs: a probabilistic and context-sensitive model of choice behavior, Psychological Review, 109, 137, 10.1037/0033-295X.109.1.137
Iverson, 1985, Statistical issues in measurement, Mathematical Social Sciences, 10, 131, 10.1016/0165-4896(85)90031-9
Iverson, G.J., & Myung, J.I. (2010). Intransitivity of preference: Revisited. Working paper. Available from Geoffrey J. Iverson, Institute for Mathematical Behavioral Sciences, UCI, Irvine, CA 92697.
Johnson, 2005, A dynamic, computational model of preference reversal phenomena, Psychological Review, 112, 841, 10.1037/0033-295X.112.4.841
Kahneman, 1979, Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk, Econometrica, 47, 263, 10.2307/1914185
Leland, 1994, Generalized similarity judgments: an alternative explanation for choice anomalies, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 9, 151, 10.1007/BF01064183
Leland, 1998, Similarity judgments in choice under uncertainty: a re-interpretation of the predictions of regret theory, Management Science, 44, 659, 10.1287/mnsc.44.5.659
Lopes, 1999, The role of aspiration level in risky choice: a comparison of cumulative prospect theory and SP/A theory, Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 43, 286, 10.1006/jmps.1999.1259
Loomes, 1991, Observing violations of transitivity by experimental methods, Econometrica, 59, 425, 10.2307/2938263
Loomes, 1982, Regret theory: an alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty, Economic Journal, 92, 805, 10.2307/2232669
Luce, 1956, Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination, Econometrica, 24, 178, 10.2307/1905751
Luce, 2000
Luce, 1991, Rank- and sign-dependent linear utility models for finite first order gambles, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 4, 29, 10.1007/BF00057885
Luce, 1995, A note on deriving rank-dependent utility using additive joint receipts, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 11, 5, 10.1007/BF01132728
Marley, 2001, Rank-weighted utilities and qualitative convolution, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 23, 135, 10.1023/A:1011132102314
Marley, 2005, Independence properties vis-à-vis several utility representations, Theory and Decision, 58, 77, 10.1007/s11238-005-2460-4
Quiggin, 1993
Regenwetter, M., Dana, J., & Davis-Stober, C. (2010). Transitivity of Preferences. Psychological Review, in press.
Rieskamp, 2006, Extending the bounds of rationality: a review of research on preferential choice, Journal of Economic Literature, 35, 631, 10.1257/jel.44.3.631
Rubinstein, 1988, Similarity and decision-making under risk (Is there a utility theory resolution to the Allais paradox?), Journal of Economic Theory, 46, 145, 10.1016/0022-0531(88)90154-8
Sopher, 1993, Intransitive cycles: rational Choice or random error? An answer based on estimation of error rates with experimental data, Theory and Decision, 35, 311, 10.1007/BF01075203
Starmer, 2000, Developments in non-expected utility theory: the hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk, Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332, 10.1257/jel.38.2.332
Stevenson, 1991, Judgment and decision-making theory, 283
Tversky, 1969, Intransitivity of preferences, Psychological Review, 76, 31, 10.1037/h0026750
Tversky, 1992, Advances in prospect theory: cumulative representation of uncertainty, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297, 10.1007/BF00122574
Weber, 2007, The effects of losses and event splitting on the Allais paradox, Judgment and Decision Making, 2, 115, 10.1017/S1930297500000097
Wu, 2004, Decision under risk, 399
Zhang, 2006, The majority rule in individual decision making, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 99, 102, 10.1016/j.obhdp.2005.06.004