Structuring embodied minds: attention and perceptual agency
Tóm tắt
Từ khóa
Tài liệu tham khảo
Barnhart, A. S., Costela, F. M., Martinez-Conde, S., Macknik, S. L., & Goldinger, S. D. (n.d.) (Eds.). Microsaccades reflect the dynamics of misdirected attention in magic. Journal of Eye Movement Research, 12(6), https://doi.org/10.16910/jemr.12.6.7. https://doi.org/10.16910/jemr.12.6.7.
Bruineberg, J., & Rietveld, E. (2014). Self-organization free energy minimization and optimal grip on a field of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 10. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00599
Bruineberg, J., & van den Herik, J. C. (2021). Embodying mental affordances. Inquiry, 1–21. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2021.1987316
Cherry, E. C. (1953). Some experiments on the recognition of speech, with one and with two ears. The Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 25(5), 975–979. https://doi.org/10.1121/1.1907229
Cisek, P., & Kalaska, J. F. (2010). Neural mechanisms for interacting with a world full of action choices. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 33(1), 269–298. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.neuro.051508.135409
Craighero, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). CHAPTER 31—The Premotor Theory of Attention. In L. Itti, G. Rees, & J. K. Tsotsos (Eds.), Neurobiology of Attention (pp. 181–186). Academic Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/B978-012375731-9/50035-5
Craighero, L., Nascimben, M., & Fadiga, L. (2004). Eye position affects orienting of visuospatial attention. Current Biology, 14(4), 331–333. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cub.2004.01.054
Crowther, T. (2009). Watching, sight, and the temporal shape of perceptual activity. The Philosophical Review, 118(1), 1–27. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2008-027
Crowther, T. (2010). X—The agential profile of perceptual experience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Hardback), 110(2pt2), 219–242. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9264.2010.00285.x
de Haan S. (2020). Enactive psychiatry. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108685214
Desimone, R., & Duncan, J. (1995). Neural mechanisms of selective visual attention. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 18(1), 193–222.
Dreyfus, H. (2002). Intelligence without representation—Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation the relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 367–383.
Eilan, N. (2006). II—Naomi Eilan on the role of perceptial consciousness in explaining the goals and mechanisms in vision: A convergence of attention? Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 80(1), 67–88.
Engbert, R., & Kliegl, R. (2003). Microsaccades uncover the orientation of covert attention. Vision Research, 43(9), 1035–1045. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0042-6989(03)00084-1
Gibson, J. J. (1976). The myth of passive perception: A reply to Richards. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 37(2), 234–238. https://doi.org/10.2307/2107194
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin.
Gibson, E., & Rader, N. (1979). Attention. In G. A. Hale & M. Lewis (Eds.), Attention and Cognitive Development (pp. 1–21). Springer US. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4613-2985-5_1
Hackley, S. A. (2015). Evidence for a vestigial pinna-orienting system in humans. Psychophysiology, 52(10), 1263–1270. https://doi.org/10.1111/psyp.12501
Hafed, Z. M., & Clark, J. J. (2002). Microsaccades as an overt measure of covert attention shifts. Vision Research, 42(22), 2533–2545. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0042-6989(02)00263-8
Hurley, S. L. (1998a). Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press.
Hurley, S. L. (1998b). Vehicles, contents, conceptual structure, and externalism. Analysis, 58(1), 1–6.
Levy, Y. (2019). What is ‘mental action’? Philosophical Psychology, 32(6), 969–991. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2019.1632427
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phenomenology of perception, trans. Colin Smith. Routledge.
Mole, C. (2011). Attention is cognitive unison: An essay in philosophical psychology. Oxford University Press.
Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. MIT press.
O’Shaughnessy, B. (1981). The Will: A dual aspect theory. Cambridge University Press.
Peacocke, C. (2007). Mental action and self-awareness (I). Contemporary Debates in the Philosophy of Mind, 358–376.
Peacocke, A. (2021). Mental action. Philosophy Compass, 16(6), e12741. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12741
Posner, M. I. (1980). Orienting of attention. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 32(1), 3–25. https://doi.org/10.1080/00335558008248231
Richards, R. J. (1976). James Gibson’s passive theory of perception: A rejection of the doctrine of specific nerve energies. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 37(2), 218–233. https://doi.org/10.2307/2107193
Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26(4), 325–352. https://doi.org/10.1080/10407413.2014.958035
Rizzolatti, G., Riggio, L., Dascola, I., & Umiltá, C. (1987). Reorienting attention across the horizontal and vertical meridians: Evidence in favor of a premotor theory of attention. Neuropsychologia, 25(1, Part 1), 31–40. https://doi.org/10.1016/0028-3932(87)90041-8
Rolfs, M. (2009). Microsaccades: Small steps on a long way. Vision Research, 49(20), 2415–2441. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.visres.2009.08.010
Ryan, A. E., Keane, B., & Wallis, G. (2019). Microsaccades and covert attention: Evidence from a continuous, divided attention task. Journal of Eye Movement Research, 12(6). https://doi.org/10.16910/jemr.12.6.6. Article 6.
Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Hutchinson.
Shepherd, J. (2014). The contours of control. Philosophical Studies, 170(3), 395–411. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0236-1
Smith, D. T., & Schenk, T. (2012). The premotor theory of attention: Time to move on? Neuropsychologia, 50(6), 1104–1114. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2012.01.025
Soteriou, M. (2009). Mental Agency, conscious thinking, and phenomenal character. In L. O’Brien, & M. Soteriou (Eds.), Mental actions (pp. 231–252). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199225989.003.0012
Soteriou, M. (2013). The mind’s construction: The ontology of mind and mental action (First edition). Oxford University Press.
Stekelenburg, J., & van Boxtel, A. (2002). Pericranial muscular, respiratory, and heart rate components of the orienting response. Psychophysiology, 39(6), 707–722. https://doi.org/10.1111/1469-8986.3960707
Strauss, D. J., Corona-Strauss, F. I., Schroeer, A., Flotho, P., Hannemann, R., & Hackley, S. A. (2020). Vestigial auriculomotor activity indicates the direction of auditory attention in humans. ELife, 9, e54536. https://doi.org/10.7554/eLife.54536
Strawson, G. (2003). XI—Mental ballistics or the involuntariness of spontaneity. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Hardback), 103(1), 227–256.
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press.
Watzl, S. (2011). The nature of attention. Philosophy Compass, 6(11), 842–853. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00433.x
Watzl, S. (2014). Perceptual guidance: Perceptual guidance. Ratio, 27(4), 414–438. https://doi.org/10.1111/rati.12084
Watzl, S. (2017). Structuring mind: The nature of attention and how it shapes consciousness. Oxford University Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Blackwell.
Wu, W. (2022). Attending as Mental Action: Mental Action as Attending. Mental Action and the conscious mind. Routledge.