Convergent evolution and the limits of natural selection

European Journal for Philosophy of Science - Tập 2 Số 3 - Trang 355-373 - 2012
Russell Powell1
1Philosophy Department, Boston University, 745 Commonwealth Avenue, Boston, MA, 02215, USA

Tóm tắt

Từ khóa


Tài liệu tham khảo

Abouheif, E. (2008). Parallelism as the pattern and process of mesoevolution. Evolution and Development, 10(1), 3–5.

Amundson, R. (1994). Two concepts of constraint: adaptationism and the challenge from developmental biology. Philosophy of Science, 61, 556–578.

Arendt, J., & Reznick, D. (2007). Convergence and parallelism reconsidered: what have we learned about the genetics of adaptation? Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 23(1), 26–32.

Beatty, J. (1995). The evolutionary contingency thesis. In G. Wolters & J. Lennox (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

Beatty, J. (2006). Replaying life’s tape. Journal of Philosophy, 103(7), 336–362.

Bolker, J. A., & Raff, R. A. (1996). Developmental genetics and traditional homology. Bioessays, 18(6), 489–494.

Brandon, R. N., & McShea, D. (2012). Biology’s first law: The tendency for diversity and complexity to increase in evolutionary systems. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Budd, G. E. (2001). Tardigrades as ‘Stem-Group Arthropods’: the evidence from the Cambrian Fauna. Zoologischer Anzeiger, 240(3–4), 265–279.

Burkhardt, F., Browne, J., Porter, D. M., & Richmond, M. (Eds.). (1993). The correspondence of Charles Darwin: Volume 8, 1860. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Caldwell, M. W. (2002). From fins to limbs to fins: limb evolution in fossil marine reptiles. American Journal of Medical Genetics, 112, 236–249.

Carroll, S. B. (2005). Endless forms most beautiful. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.

Conway Morris, S. (1998). The crucible of creation: The Burgess Shale and the rise of animals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Conway Morris, S. (2003). Life’s solution: Inevitable humans in a lonely universe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Conway Morris, S., & Gould, S. J. (1998). Showdown on the Burgess Shale. Natural History, 107(10), 48–55.

Dawkins, R. (1986). The blind watchmaker. New York: Norton.

Davidson, E. H., & Erwin, D. H. (2006). Gene regulatory networks and the evolution of animal body plans. Science, 311, 796–800.

Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Diogo, R. (2005). Evolutionary convergences and parallelisms: their theoretical differences and the difficulty of discriminating them in a practical context. Biology and Philosophy, 20, 735–744.

Donley, J. M., et al. (2004). Convergent evolution in mechanical design of lamnid sharks and tunas. Nature, 429, 61–65.

Foster, S. A., & Baker, J. A. (2004). Evolution in parallel: new insights from a classic system. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 19, 456–459.

Gibson, G., & Wagner, G. (2000). Canalization in evolutionary genetics: a stabilizing theory? BioEssays, 22, 372–380.

Goodwin, B. C. (2001). How the leopard changed its spots: The evolution of complexity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Gould, S. J. (1989). Wonderful life: The Burgess Shale and the nature of history. New York: Norton.

Gould, S. J. (2002). The structure of evolutionary theory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Gould, S. J., & Lewontin, R. C. (1979). The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society, London, 205(1161), 581–598.

Hall, B. K. (2007). Homology or homoplasy: dichotomy or continuum? Journal of Human Evolution, 52, 473–479.

Jablonksi, D. (2002). Survival without recovery after mass extinctions. PNAS, 99, 8139–8144.

Land, M. F., & Fernald, R. D. (1992). The evolution of eyes. Annual Review Neuroscience, 15, 1–29.

Lewens, T. (2009). Seven types of adaptationism. Biology and Philosophy, 24, 161–182.

Lloyd, E. A. (2005). The case of the female orgasm: Bias in evolutionary science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Losos, J. B., Jackman, T. R., Larson, A., de Queiroz, K., & Rodríguez-Schettino, L. (1998). Contingency and determinism in replicated adaptive radiations of Island Lizards. Science, 279(5359), 2115–2118.

Maclaurin, J., & Sterelny, K. (2008). What is biodiversity? Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Martin, L. D., & Meehan, T. J. (2005). Extinction may not be forever. Naturwissenschaften, 92(1), 1–19.

Millstein, R. L. (2000). Chance and macroevolution. Philosophy of Science, 67, 603–624.

Orzack, S., & Sober, E. (1994). Optimality models and the test of adaptationism. American Naturalist, 143, 361–380.

Pearce, T. (in press). Convergence and parallelism in evolution—A neo Gouldian account. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

Powell, R. (2007). Is convergence more than an analogy? Homoplasy and its implications for macroevolutionary predictability. Biology and Philosophy, 22, 565–578.

Powell, R. (2009). “Contingency and Convergence in Macroevolution.” Journal of Philosophy, 106(7), 390–404.

Rosenberg, A. (2001). How is biological explanation possible? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52(4), 735–760.

Sanger, T. J., Losos, J. B., & Gibson-Brown, J. J. (2008). A developmental staging series for the lizard genus Anolis: a new system for the integration of evolution, development, and ecology. Journal of Morphology, 269(2), 129.

Shapiro, M. D., Marks, M. E., Peichel, C. L., Blackman, B. K., Nereng, K. S., Jónsson, B., et al. (2004). Genetic and developmental basis of evolutionary pelvic reduction in threespine sticklebacks. Nature, 428, 717–723.

Shapiro, M. D., Bell, M. A., & Kingsley, D. M. (2006). Parallel genetic origins of pelvic reduction in vertebrates. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 103(37), 13753–13758.

Sober, E. (2005). Is drift a serious alternative to natural selection when it comes to explaining adaptive complexity? In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Philosophy, biology and life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Stayton, C. T. (2008). Is convergence surprising? An examination of the frequency of convergence in simulated datasets. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 252, 1–14.

Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Sex and death: an introduction to philosophy of biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Thattai, M., & van Oudenaarden, A. (2001). Intrinsic noise in gene regulatory networks. PNAS, 98, 8614.

Valentine, J. W., & Erwin, D. H. (1987). Interpreting great developmental experiments: the fossil record. In R. A. Raff & E. C. Raff (Eds.), Development as an evolutionary process (pp. 71–107). New York: Liss.

Vermeij, G. J. (2006). Historical contingency and the purported uniqueness of evolutionary innovations. PNAS, 103(6), 1804–1809.

Wagner, G. P. (1988). The influence of variation and of developmental constraints on the rate of multivariate phenotypic evolution. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 1, 45–66.

Wagner, G. P., & Schwenk, K. (2000). Evolutionarily stable configurations: functional integration and the evolution of phenotypic stability. Evolutionary Biology, 31, 155–217.

Wake, D. B. (1991). Homoplasy: the result of natural selection, or evidence of design limitation. American Naturalist, 138, 543–567.

Waters, K. (2007). Causes that make a difference. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 551–579.

Williams, G. C. (1985). A defense of reductionism in evolutionary biology. In R. Dawkins & M. Ridley (Eds.), Oxford surveys in evolutionary biology, vol. 2 (pp. 1–27). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Zuker, C. S. (1994). On the evolution of eyes: would you like it simple or compound? Science, 265, 742–743.