A better world

Springer Science and Business Media LLC - Tập 168 - Trang 629-644 - 2013
Ryan Preston-Roedder1
1Department of Philosophy, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill, Chapel Hill, USA

Tóm tắt

A number of moral philosophers have endorsed instances of the following curious argument: it would be better if a certain moral theory were true; therefore, we have reason to believe that the theory is true. In other words, the mere truth of the theory—quite apart from the results of our believing it or acting in accord with it—would make for a better world than the truth of its rivals, and this fact provides evidence of the theory’s truth. This form of argument may seem to be an obvious non-starter. After all, the fact that the truth of some empirical claim, say, the claim that there is an afterlife, would be desirable does not, by itself, give us any reason to believe it. But I argue that, when it is properly understood, this form of argument—which I call the better world argument—is valid in moral philosophy. I develop and defend a version of the argument that rests on the view that the correct moral theory cannot exhibit a certain form of self-defeat—a form that, as far as I know, has not been discussed in the literature. I also identify two promising applications of this form of argument. The first is a defense of permissions to promote one’s own private aims, rather than promote the greater good, and the second, an argument against the possibility of moral dilemmas.

Tài liệu tham khảo

Baier, K. (1958). The moral point of view. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Enoch, D. (2009). Wouldn’t it be nice if p, therefore p (for a moral p). Utilitas, 21, 222–224. Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking: Its levels, methods and point. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kagan, S. (1989). The limits of morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kagan, S. (1991). Responses to my critics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 51, 919–928. Kamm, F. M. (1996). Morality, mortality: Volume II: Rights, duties, and status. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kamm, F. M. (2007). Intricate ethics: Rights, responsibilities, and permissible harm. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McNaughton, D., & Rawling, P. (1998). On defending deontology. Ratio, 11, 37–54. Nagel, T. (1995). Personal rights and public space. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 24, 83–107. Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Quinn, W. (1993). Actions, intentions and consequences: The doctrine of doing and allowing. In Morality and action (pp. 149–174). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (revised edition). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sartre, J. (1975). Existentialism is a humanism. In W. Kaufman (Ed.), Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre (revised and expanded edition). New York: Penguin Group. Shiffrin, S. (1991). Moral autonomy and agent-centered options. Analysis, 51, 244–254. Sidgwick, H. (1907). The methods of ethics (7th ed.). London: Macmillan. Slote, M. (1985). Common-sense morality and consequentialism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Unger, P. (1996). Living high and letting die: Our illusion of innocence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. van Someren Greve, R. (2011). Wishful thinking in moral theorizing: Comment on Enoch. Utilitas, 23, 447–450. Walker, M. (1991). Moral luck and the virtues of impure agency. Metaphilosophy, 22(1 and 2), 14–21.