The empirical case against introspection

Springer Science and Business Media LLC - Tập 173 - Trang 2461-2485 - 2016
Rik Peels1
1Philosophy Department, VU University Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

Tóm tắt

This paper assesses five main empirical scientific arguments against the reliability of belief formation on the basis of introspecting phenomenal states. After defining ‘reliability’ and ‘introspection’, I discuss five arguments to the effect that phenomenal states are more elusive than we usually think: (1) the argument on the basis of differences in introspective reports from differences in introspective measurements; (2) the argument from differences in reports about whether or not dreams come in colours; (3) the argument from the absence of a correlation between visual imagery ability and the performance on certain cognitive tasks; (4) the argument from our unawareness of our capacity of echolocation; (5) the argument from inattentional blindness and change blindness. I argue that the experiments on which these arguments are based do not concern belief formation on the basis of introspection in the first place or fail to show that it is unreliable, even when limited to introspection of phenomenal states.

Tài liệu tham khảo

Angell, J. R. (1910). Methods for the determination of mental imagery. Psychological Monographs, 13, 61–108. Audi, R. (1994). Dispositional beliefs and dispositions to believe. Noûs, 28(4), 419–434. Bentley, M. (1915). The study of dreams: A method adapted to the seminary. The American Journal of Psychology, 26(2), 196–210. Bode, B. H. (1913). The method of introspection. Journal of Philosophy, 10(4), 85–91. Byrne, A. (2005). Introspection. Philosophical Topics, 33(1), 79–104. Chalmers, D. J. (2003). The content and epistemology of phenomenal belief. In Q. Smith & A. Jokic (Eds.), Consciousness: New philosophical perspectives (pp. 220–272). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dennett, D. C. (1969). Content and consciousness. London: Routledge. Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. London: The Penguin Press. Dennett, D. C. (2001). Surprise, surprise. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 982. Dennett, D. C. (2007). Heterophenomenology reconsidered. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(1-2), 247–270. Ericsson, K. A. (2003). Valid and non-reactive verbalization of thoughts during performance of tasks: Towards a solution to the central problems of introspection as a source of scientific data. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 1–18. Escalas, J. E. (2004). Imagine yourself in the product: Mental simulation, narrative transportation, and persuasion. Journal of Advertising, 33(2), 37–48. Gallagher, S. (2003). Phenomenology and experimental design: Toward a phenomenologically enlightened experimental science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 85–99. Galton, F. (1880). Statistics of mental imagery. Mind, 5(19), 301–318. Gemignani, A., Sebastiani, L., Simoni, A., Santarcangelo, E. L., & Ghelarducci, B. (2006). Hypnotic trait and specific phobia: EEG and autonomic output during phobic stimulation. Brain Research Bulletin, 69(2), 197–203. Grimes, J. (1996). On the failure to detect changes in scenes across saccades. In E. Akins (Ed.), Perception (pp. 89–110). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hausfeld, S., Power, R. P., Gorta, A., & Harris, P. (1982). Echo perception of shape and texture by sighted subjects. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 55(2), 623–632. Hurlburt, R. T., & Heavey, C. L. (2001). Telling what we know: Describing inner experience. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(9), 400–403. Irvine, E. (2012). Old problems with new measures in the science of consciousness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 627–648. Irvine, E. (2013). Measures of consciousness. Philosophy Compass, 8(3), 285–297. Jack, A. I., & Roepstorff, A. (2003). “Editorial introduction: Why trust the subject?”, Trusting the subject: The use of introspective evidence in cognitive science, Vol. 1, Journal of Consciousness Studies 10.9-10, v-xx. Jack, A. I., & Shallice, T. (2001). Introspective physicalism as an approach to the science of consciousness. Cognition, 79(1-2), 161–196. Kriegel, U. (2013). A hesitant defense of introspection. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 1165–1176. Lobmaier, J. S., & Mast, F. W. (2008). Face imagery is based on featural representations. Experimental Psychology, 55(1), 47–53. Lutz, A., & Thompson, E. (2003). Neurophenomenology: Integrating subjective experience and brain dynamics in the neuroscience of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9-10), 31–52. Mack, A. (2003). Inattentional blindness: Looking without seeing. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 12(5), 180–184. Marcel, A. J. (1993). Slippage in the unity of consciousness. In G. R. Block & J. Marsh (Eds.), Experimental and theoretical studies of consciousness (pp. 168–186). Chichester: Wiley. Marcel, A. J. (2003). Introspective report: Trust, self-knowledge and science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11(7-8), 167–186. McKelvie, S. J. (1995). The VVIQ and beyond: Vividness and its measurement. Journal of Mental Imagery, 19(3), 197–252. Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. O’Regan, J. K. (1992). Solving the “Real” mysteries of visual perception: The world as an outside memory. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 46(3), 461–488. Overgaard, M. (2006). Introspection in science. Consciousness and Cognition, 15(4), 629–633. Paivio, A. (1990). Mental representations: A dual coding approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Peels, R. (2016). A conceptual map of scientism. In J. Rik Peels & R. van Woudenberg (Eds.), Scientism: A philosophical exposition and evaluation. New York: Oxford University Press (Forthcoming). Petrova, P. K., & Cialdini, R. B. (2005). Fluency of consumption imagery and the backfire effects of imagery appeals. Journal of Consumer Research, 32(3), 442–452. Price, H. H. (1954). Perception. London: Methuen. Rensink, R. A., O’Regan, J. K., & Clark, J. J. (1997). To see or not to see: The need for attention to perceive changes in scenes. Psychological Science, 8(5), 368–373. Richardson, J. T. E. (1980). Mental imagery and human memory. London: MacMillan Press. Rosenberg, A. (2011). The atheist's guide to reality: Enjoying life without illusions. New York: W.W. Norton. Rosenblum, L. D., Gordon, M. S., & Jarquin, L. (2000). Echolocating distance by moving and stationary listeners. Ecological Psychology, 12(3), 181–206. Schwitzgebel, E. (2007). No unchallengeable epistemic authority, of any sort, regarding our own conscious experience—Contra Dennett? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(1-2), 107–113. Schwitzgebel, E. (2010). “Introspection”, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/introspection/, first published February 2nd 2010; substantive revision September 4th 2010, last visited November 24th 2015. Schwitzgebel, E. (2011). Perplexities of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Schwitzgebel, E., & Gordon, M. S. (2000). How well do we know our own conscious experience? The case of human echolocation. Philosophical Topics, 282(2), 235–246. Sheehan, P. W. (1967). A shortened form of Betts’ Questionnaire upon mental imagery. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 23(3), 386–389. Smithies, D., & Stoljar, D. (2012). Introspection and consciousness: An overview. In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness (pp. 3–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20(2), 158–177. Zihl, J., & von Cramon, D. Y. (1980). Registration of light stimuli in the cortically blind hemifield and its effect on localization. Behavioural Brain Research, 1, 287–298.